Pseudoscience: Difference between revisions
imported>Gareth Leng (re-order) |
imported>Gareth Leng |
||
Line 58: | Line 58: | ||
==The demarcation problem, and criticisms of the concept of pseudoscience== | ==The demarcation problem, and criticisms of the concept of pseudoscience== | ||
Despite broad agreement on the basics of the scientific method, the boundaries between science and non-science continue to be debated.<ref>Cover JA, Curd M (Eds, 1998) ''Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues'' 1-82</ref> This is the [[scientific method#Problem of demarcation|''problem of demarcation'']]. | Despite broad agreement on the basics of the scientific method, the boundaries between science and non-science continue to be debated.<ref>Cover JA, Curd M (Eds, 1998) ''Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues'' 1-82</ref> This is the [[scientific method#Problem of demarcation|''problem of demarcation'']]. The defining feature of science is not experimental success, for, in Rothbart's words, "most clear cases of genuine science have been experimentally falsified". <ref>Rothbart D "Demarcating Genuine Science from Pseudoscience", in Grim ''op cit'' p 114</ref> Many disciplines currently thought of as science exhibited at some time in their history, features which are often cited as flaws of scientific method, and many currently accepted scientific theories — including the theory of [[evolution]], [[plate tectonics]], the [[Big Bang]] (a term originally chosen by [[Fred Hoyle]] to poke fun at the idea), and [[quantum mechanics]] — were criticized as being pseudo-scientific when first proposed. In retrospect, it is clear that this was a response to the challenge they posed to accepted doctrines, and a reflection of the difficulty in gathering evidence for new theories. Further, because of the heterogeneous nature of the scientific enterprise itself, it is difficult to create a set of criteria which can be applied to all disciplines at all times. | ||
Nevertheless, over the years there have been repeated efforts by philosophers of science to propose demarcation criteria. [[Logical positivism]], proposed that only statements about [[Empirical knowledge|empirical]] observations are meaningful, thus asserting that all [[metaphysics|metaphysical]] statements) are meaningless. Later, [[Karl Popper]] attacked logical positivism and introduced a different criterion, [[falsifiability]]. This in turn was criticised by the historian of science [[Thomas Kuhn]], who argued that falsification had in fact played little part in scientific"revolutions", and by [[Imre Lakatos]], who proposed his own criteria that distinguished between progressive and "degenerative" research programs. It has been argued that experimental verification is not in itself decisive in scientific method. [[Thomas Kuhn]] states that in neither Popper's theory nor in his own does testing play a decisive role. <ref>Kuhn TS "Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?" in Grim, ''op cit'' p 125 The latter proposed that a scientific theory must "account for all the phenomena that its rival background theory explains" and "must clash empirically with its rival by yielding test implications that are inconsistent with the rival theory". This is an explicitly competitive model of scientific work; Rothbart also notes that it is not a completely effective model<ref>Rothbart, Daniel, ''op cit'' pp 114-20</ref>. | |||
Many philosophers however have questioned the rigor of any demarcation. | |||
Larry Laudan has suggested that ''pseudoscience'' has no scientific meaning: "If we would stand up and be counted on the side of reason, we ought to drop terms like ‘pseudo-science’ and ‘unscientific’ from our vocabulary; they are just hollow phrases which do only emotive work for us".<ref>Laudan L (1996) "The demise of the demarcation problem" in Ruse M ''But Is It Science?: The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution Controversy '' pp 337-350</ref> | Larry Laudan has suggested that ''pseudoscience'' has no scientific meaning: "If we would stand up and be counted on the side of reason, we ought to drop terms like ‘pseudo-science’ and ‘unscientific’ from our vocabulary; they are just hollow phrases which do only emotive work for us".<ref>Laudan L (1996) "The demise of the demarcation problem" in Ruse M ''But Is It Science?: The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution Controversy '' pp 337-350</ref> | ||
Revision as of 10:05, 2 November 2006
The term pseudoscience which combines the Greek root pseudo, meaning false, and the Latin scientia, meaning knowledge, appears to have been used first in 1843 by Magendie, who referred to phrenology as "a pseudo-science of the present day" [1] Among its early uses was in 1844 in the Northern Journal of Medicine, I 387: "That opposite kind of innovation which pronounces what has been recognized as a branch of science, to have been a pseudo-science, composed merely of so-called facts, connected together by misapprehensions under the disguise of principles".
Introduction
The conventions for determining whether a body of knowledge, methodology, or practice is "scientific" vary from field to field, but generally involve similar principles of reproducibility and intersubjective verifiability. [2] Such principles aim to ensure that evidence can be replicated, which allows further investigation to determine whether a hypothesis or theory is valid and reliable. Validated methods are expected to be applied consistently, and bias to be controlled or eliminated. Data, including experimental/environmental conditions, are expected to be documented for scrutiny and made available for peer review.
However, despite general agreement on these principles, there is disagreement about whether it is possible to distinguish "science" from "pseudoscience" in a reliable and objective way, and about whether attempting to do so is useful. The philosopher of science Paul Feyeraband in particular is associated with the view that attempts to distinguish science from non-science are flawed. "The idea that science can, and should, be run according to fixed and universal rules, is both unrealistic and pernicious. ... the idea is detrimental to science, for it neglects the complex physical and historical conditions which influence scientific change. It makes our science less adaptable and more dogmatic:"[3] [4]
Those who believe that characterising some areas as pseudoscientific is useful stress the use of vague, exaggerated or untestable claims, over-reliance on confirmation rather than refutation, lack of openness to testing by other experts, and a lack of progress in theory development. The term "pseudoscientific" is sometimes applied by disputants working in the same field to disparage a competing theory or the argument used by a rival, sometimes by commentators from outside a field to disparage a whole field, sometimes to express the opinion that a theory published in a popular book has no academic credibility [5] and sometimes in reference to a theory now discarded. [6]
The brights movement, prominently represented by Richard Dawkins, Mario Bunge, Carl Sagan and James Randi, consider that all forms of pseudoscience are harmful, whether or not they result in immediate harm to their adherents. These critics consider that pseudoscientific beliefs may be held for several reasons, from simple naïveté about the nature of science, to deception for financial or political gain. At the extreme, issues of health and safety may be involved, for example in the case of physical or mental therapy, or in assessing risks.
Defining science by the scientific method
In the mid-20th Century, Karl Popper suggested the criterion of falsifiability to distinguish science from non-science.[7] Theories may be true or false, but if they do not entail predictions that are in principle capable of falsification by experimental tests, then they are devoid of content and hence mere pseudoscience. Popper subdivided non-science into philosophical, mathematical, mythological, religious and/or metaphysical formulations on the one hand, and pseudoscientific formulations on the other[8], and gave astrology, Marxism, and Freudian psychoanalysis as examples of pseudosciences as being wholly unfalsifiable theories. [9] More recently, Paul Thagard proposed that pseudoscience can be distinguished by its lack of progress, and by the lack of serious attempts by proponents to solve problems with the theory. Mario Bunge has suggested the categories of "belief fields" and "research fields" to help distinguish between science and pseudoscience.
Defining pseudoscience
Science differs from revelation, theology, or spirituality in that it claims to offer insight into the physical world by "scientific" means. Systems of thought that derive from "divine" or "inspired" knowledge are not considered pseudoscience if they do not claim to be scientific. However, a field might plausibly be called pseudoscientific if it is presented as consistent with the accepted norms of scientific research, but demonstrably fails to meet these norms.[10]
The following have been proposed to be indicative of poor scientific reasoning.
- Vague, exaggerated or untestable claims
- Failure to use "operational definitions" (i.e. a rigorous description of the means by which measurements are made).
- Failure to use the principle of parsimony, i.e. failing to seek an explanation that requires the fewest possible additional assumptions when other viable explanations are possible (Occam's Razor)
- Use of obscurantist language, and misuse of apparently technical jargon, in an effort to give claims the superficial trappings of science.
- Lack of boundary conditions: Most well-supported scientific theories possess well articulated limitations under which predictions do or do not apply.
- Assertion of scientific claims that cannot be falsified in the event they are incorrect, inaccurate, or irrelevant [11]
- Assertion of claims that a theory predicts something that it has not been shown to predict [12]
- Assertion that claims which have not been proven false must be true, and vice versa (see: Argument from ignorance)[13]
- Over-reliance on testimonials and anecdotes. Testimonial and anecdotal evidence can be useful for discovery (hypothesis generation) but should not be used in the context of justification (hypothesis testing). [14]
- Selective use of experimental evidence: presenting data that seem to support claims while suppressing or dismissing data that contradict them.
- Reversed burden of proof. In science, the burden of proof rests on the individual making a claim, not on the critic. "Pseudoscientific" arguments may neglect this principle and demand that skeptics demonstrate beyond reasonable doubt that a claim is false.
- Evasion of peer review before publicizing results ("science by press conference"). [15]
Some proponents of theories that contradict accepted scientific theories avoid the often ego-bruising process of peer review, sometimes on the grounds that peer review is biased against claims that contradict established paradigms, and sometimes on the grounds that assertions cannot be evaluated using standard scientific methods. [16]
- Failure to provide adequate information for other researchers to reproduce claimed results.
- Assertion of claims of secrecy or proprietary knowledge in response to requests for review of data or methodology.
Lack of progress Thagard [17] proposed that a theory or discipline which has pretensions to be scientific can be regarded as pseudoscientific if (and only if): "it has been less progressive than alternative theories over a long period of time, and faces many unsolved problems; but the community of practitioners makes little attempt to develop the theory towards solutions of the problems, shows no concern for attempts to evaluate the theory in relation to others, and is selective in considering confirmations and disconfirmations" [18]
Personalization of issues
- Tight social groups and granfalloons. Authoritarian personality, suppression of dissent, and "groupthink" can enhance the adoption of beliefs that have no rational basis. The group tends to identify their critics as enemies.[19]
- Assertion of claims of a conspiracy by the scientific community to suppress the results.[20]
- Attacking the motives or character of anyone who questions the claims (Ad hominem fallacy).[19]
Some of these criticisms has also been levelled to areas regarded as part of conventional science. According to Churchland, "Most terms in theoretical physics, for example, do not enjoy at least some distinct connections with observables, but not of the simple sort that would permit operational definitions in terms of these observables. [..] If a restriction in favor of operational definitions were to be followed, therefore, most of theoretical physics would have to be dismissed as meaningless pseudoscience!" [21]
Pseudoscience and protoscience
Protoscience is a term sometimes used for a hypothesis that has not yet been adequately tested, but which is consistent with existing science or offers a plausible account of any inconsistencies. It may also describe the transition from a body of practical knowledge into a scientific field. By contrast, "pseudoscience" is reserved for theories which are untestable in practice or in principle, or which are maintained even when evidence appears to refute them.
It is widely disputed (notably by Feyeraband, see above) whether any clear or meaningful boundaries can be drawn between pseudoscience, protoscience, and "real" science. When there is a significant cultural or historical distance (as, for example, modern chemistry reflecting on alchemy), protosciences can be misinterpreted as pseudoscientific. Often the term pseudoscience is used simply as a pejorative to express a low opinion of a given field, regardless of any objective measures; thus according to McNally, "The term “pseudoscience” has become little more than an inflammatory buzzword for quickly dismissing one’s opponents in media sound-bites." [22].
The demarcation problem, and criticisms of the concept of pseudoscience
Despite broad agreement on the basics of the scientific method, the boundaries between science and non-science continue to be debated.[23] This is the problem of demarcation. The defining feature of science is not experimental success, for, in Rothbart's words, "most clear cases of genuine science have been experimentally falsified". [24] Many disciplines currently thought of as science exhibited at some time in their history, features which are often cited as flaws of scientific method, and many currently accepted scientific theories — including the theory of evolution, plate tectonics, the Big Bang (a term originally chosen by Fred Hoyle to poke fun at the idea), and quantum mechanics — were criticized as being pseudo-scientific when first proposed. In retrospect, it is clear that this was a response to the challenge they posed to accepted doctrines, and a reflection of the difficulty in gathering evidence for new theories. Further, because of the heterogeneous nature of the scientific enterprise itself, it is difficult to create a set of criteria which can be applied to all disciplines at all times.
Nevertheless, over the years there have been repeated efforts by philosophers of science to propose demarcation criteria. Logical positivism, proposed that only statements about empirical observations are meaningful, thus asserting that all metaphysical statements) are meaningless. Later, Karl Popper attacked logical positivism and introduced a different criterion, falsifiability. This in turn was criticised by the historian of science Thomas Kuhn, who argued that falsification had in fact played little part in scientific"revolutions", and by Imre Lakatos, who proposed his own criteria that distinguished between progressive and "degenerative" research programs. It has been argued that experimental verification is not in itself decisive in scientific method. Thomas Kuhn states that in neither Popper's theory nor in his own does testing play a decisive role. Cite error: Closing </ref>
missing for <ref>
tag.
Many philosophers however have questioned the rigor of any demarcation. Larry Laudan has suggested that pseudoscience has no scientific meaning: "If we would stand up and be counted on the side of reason, we ought to drop terms like ‘pseudo-science’ and ‘unscientific’ from our vocabulary; they are just hollow phrases which do only emotive work for us".[25]
The ubiquity of pseudoscientific thinking
The National Science Foundation stated that, in the USA, "pseudoscientific" beliefs became more widespread during the 1990's, peaked near 2001 and mildly declined since; nevertheless, pseudoscientific beliefs remain common in the USA.[26] As a result, according to the NSF report, there is a lack of knowledge of pseudoscientific issues in society and pseudoscientific practices are commonly followed. Bunge (1999) stated that a 1988 survey showed that 50% of American adults rejected evolution, and 88% believed that astrology was a science.
Pseudoscientific thinking has been explained in terms of psychology and social psychology. The human proclivity for seeking confirmation rather than refutation (confirmation bias) [27], the tendency to hold comforting beliefs, and the tendency to overgeneralize have been proposed as reasons for the common adherence to pseudoscientific thinking.
Pseudoscience in psychology
Some neurologists and clinical psychologists [28] are concerned about the increasing amount of what they consider pseudoscience in psychotherapy and popular psychology, and that "pseudoscientific" therapies such as Neuro-linguistic programming, Rebirthing, Reparenting, and Primal Scream Therapy are being increasingly adopted. They state that scientifically unsupported therapies might harm vulnerable members of the public, undermine legitimate therapies, and spread misconceptions about the nature of the mind and brain. Some psychiatrists and psychologists also perceive pseudoscientific ideas in more popularly accepted branches of psychotherapy, such as co-counselling, Gestalt Therapy, Re-evaluation Counseling and even in the work of Twelve-step program bodies such as Alcoholics Anonymous.
Notes
- ↑ Magendie, F (1843) An Elementary Treatise on Human Physiology. 5th Ed. Tr. John Revere. New York, Harper, p 150
- ↑ Gauch HG Jr (2003) Scientific Method in Practice
- ↑ Feyerabend P (1975) Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge [1]
- ↑ [2]
- ↑ [3][4]
- ↑ e.g. phrenology, see [ http://www.theness.com/articles.asp?id=40]
- ↑ Popper, KR (1959) "The Logic of Scientific Discovery" (English translation, 1959)[5].
- ↑ Popper KR "Science: Conjectures and Refutations"
- ↑ Popper KR (1962) Science, Pseudo-Science, and Falsifiability. Conjectures and Refutations
- ↑ Cover JA, Curd M (Eds, 1998) Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues, 1-82
- ↑ Lakatos I (1970) "Falsification and the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes." in Lakatos I, Musgrave A (eds) Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge pp 91-195; Popper KR (1959) The Logic of Scientific Discovery
- ↑ e.g. [6] Macmilllan Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3, "Fallacies" 174 'ff, esp. section on "Ignoratio elenchi"
- ↑ Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 3, "Fallacies" 174 'ff esp. 177-178
- ↑ Bunge M (1983) Demarcating science from pseudoscience Fundamenta Scientiae 3:369-388, 381
- ↑ Peer review and the acceptance of new scientific ideas (Warning 469 kB PDF)*Peer review – process, perspectives and the path ahead; Lilienfeld (2004) op cit For an opposing perspective, e.g. Peer Review as Scholarly Conformity
- ↑ Ruscio J (2001) Clear thinking with psychology: Separating sense from nonsense. Pacific Grove, CA: Wadsworth
- ↑ Thagard (1978) op cit
- ↑ name=Ruscio120>Ruscio J (2001) op cit. p120.The work Scientists Confront Velikovsky (1976) Cornell University, also delves into these features in some detail, as does the work of Thomas Kuhn, e.g. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962).
- ↑ 19.0 19.1 Devilly GJ (2005) Power therapies and possible threats to the science of psychology and psychiatry Austral NZ J Psych 39:437-445(9) Cite error: Invalid
<ref>
tag; name "Devilly" defined multiple times with different content - ↑ e.g. archivefreedom.org which claims that "The list of suppressed scientists even includes Nobel Laureates!"
- ↑ Churchland P Matter and Consciousness: A Contemporary Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind (1999) MIT Press. p.90.
- ↑ McNally RJ (2003)Is the pseudoscience concept useful for clinical psychology? SRHMP Vol 2 Number 2 Fall/Winter [7]
- ↑ Cover JA, Curd M (Eds, 1998) Philosophy of Science: The Central Issues 1-82
- ↑ Rothbart D "Demarcating Genuine Science from Pseudoscience", in Grim op cit p 114
- ↑ Laudan L (1996) "The demise of the demarcation problem" in Ruse M But Is It Science?: The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution Controversy pp 337-350
- ↑ [8] National Science Board. 2006. Science and Engineering Indicators 2006 Two volumes. Arlington, VA: National Science Foundation (volume 1, NSB-06-01; NSB 06-01A)
- ↑ (Devilly 2005:439)
- ↑ e.g. Drenth (2003) [9]; Herbert JD et al (2000) Science and pseudoscience in the development of eye movement desensitization and reprocessing: implications for clinical psychology Clin Psychol Rev 20:945-71 [PMID 11098395])
External links
- The Anatomy of Pseudoscience - Steven Novella, MD
- Science and Pseudoscience - transcript and broadcast of talk by Imre Lakatos
- Science Needs to Combat Pseudoscience - A statement by 32 Russian scientists and philosophers