Gene: Difference between revisions
imported>Meg Taylor m (spelling: noticible -> noticeable) |
imported>Meg Taylor m (spelling: posess -> possess) |
||
Line 54: | Line 54: | ||
An organism with two identical copies is said to be [[homozygous]] for that gene, and is called a homozygote. An organism with two different alleles for a gene is said to be [[heterozygous]] for that gene, and is called a heterozygote. | An organism with two identical copies is said to be [[homozygous]] for that gene, and is called a homozygote. An organism with two different alleles for a gene is said to be [[heterozygous]] for that gene, and is called a heterozygote. | ||
In a heterozygote, when one allele determines the appearance of the individual it is called the dominant allele. When the other has no noticeable effect it is called the recessive allele. Another term sometimes used for homozygous organisms is "true breeding" because of the certainty that their offspring will | In a heterozygote, when one allele determines the appearance of the individual it is called the dominant allele. When the other has no noticeable effect it is called the recessive allele. Another term sometimes used for homozygous organisms is "true breeding" because of the certainty that their offspring will possess the given trait. The appearance of a given trait is referred to as the [[phenotype]] of the individual, whereas the complete set of alleles (dominant ''and'' recessive) is referred to as the [[genotype]]. | ||
In reality, a more complex combination of gene expression is common. In some cases, the offspring's appearance is found to be ''in between'' the two appearances. This can be seen in cases such as [[hybrids]] of red and white [[roses]] that can appear pink. This phenomonon is called [[incomplete dominance]]. | In reality, a more complex combination of gene expression is common. In some cases, the offspring's appearance is found to be ''in between'' the two appearances. This can be seen in cases such as [[hybrids]] of red and white [[roses]] that can appear pink. This phenomonon is called [[incomplete dominance]]. |
Revision as of 01:30, 11 February 2010
A gene (from the Greek γεννάω gennao, to beget or produce) is generally viewed as the basic physical and functional unit of heredity.[2] Genes, which are made up of DNA, act as blueprints to make molecules called proteins. Scientists sometimes consider other segments of DNA genes as well, such as the segments that encode blueprints for nucleotide polymer structures like ribosomal RNA (rRNA) and transfer RNA (tRNA), or DNA sites at which information concerned with gene regulation and expression is located.
Genes defined?
Throughout the biological disciplines, the word 'gene' refers to some heritable 'entity' or 'system', related to DNA, that plays a role in the development of characteristics of individual organisms and a role, over an evolutionary timescale, in the development of species. That definition, with all its lack of specificity, and perhaps because of that lack of specificity, seems hardly disputable, though likely editable.
Can we define 'gene' more precisely? It would appear that we can, but in doing so we find more than one more-or-less precise definition of 'gene', or 'gene concept', each having a different meaning, in the semantic sense that "[w]ords mean the thing they make us think of...."[3] Biologists think of different things in relation to the word 'gene', and therefore employ a multiplicity of concepts of genes.[4] [5] [6]
Neumann-Held[4] contrasts the 'evolutionary gene concept' with the 'classical molecular gene concept'. She notes that in Richard Dawkins’ 'evolutionary genes concept' genes are defined not in terms of the polypeptides they produce but in terms of differences in phenotypes among individuals of a population, which affect their fitness as measured by reproductive success. In evolutionary genes, differences in DNA sequence might affect fitness, but not necessarily polypeptide production. Evolutionary genes need not even produce polypeptides. Moreover, heritable differences that might affect fitness need not involve differences in DNA sequences, as there are more dimensions to evolution than DNA sequence changes (e.g., epigenetic changes). ‘Evolutionary’ genes, thus, need not involve DNA sequence changes.
Griffiths and Stotz[5] describe three different concepts of the gene:
- Instrumental genes: "factors in a model of the transmission of a heritable phenotype, or in a population genetic model of a changing population." They permit formal mathematical analyses of inheritance and gene frequency changes in populations.
- Nominal genes: "specific DNA sequences that are annotated as genes because of their similarity to the sequences that were the focus of study as biologists uncovered the functions of DNA from the mid-1950s to the 1970s." These sequences have formal names.
- Postgenomic molecular genes: "collections of DNA elements that play the role of the gene as envisaged in early molecular biology—acting as templates for the synthesis of gene products—but which are not nominal genes, because the way in which DNA is used in the production of the relevant gene products does not fit the traditional stereotype."
Lenny Moss writes:
If a gene (assuming that this term can even be given anything like a univocal referent) provides only a resource from which any number of both noncoding regulatory as well as highly splice variable coding sequences are derived, all of which may contribute in context-sensitive ways to a vast multiplicity of biological sequelae, then how sensible is it to think of genes as representations, not to mention causes, of discrete phenotypic outcomes? [6] |
Degeng Wang writes:
A gene, I argue, should be interpreted as a functional unit that is responsible for the trans-generation passage of the capacity to dynamically produce a biochemical activity or biochemical activities....Instead of a context-dependent definition of the gene, I argue for the view that it is the same gene displaying multiple meanings, subject to differential interpretation by the cellular machinery in different states. In other words, the same gene gives rise to different products and expression levels under different conditions. [7] |
It seems that the biologist's goal, methodologies, and findings determine her concept of the gene. Only an historical account of the evolution of the concept of the gene can make sense of this 'gene concept' diversity.
History and evolution of the concept of the gene
Chromosomes
In eukaryotes (organisms whose cells have nuclei, such as plants, yeasts and animals), genes are usually arranged together in multiple long thread-like arrangements called chromosomes. Chromosomes typically come in pairs, and there can be hundreds, sometimes thousands, of genes in one chromosome. Prokaryotes (organisms such as common bacteria) generally have a single large circular chromosome, but often possess other miniature chromosomes called plasmids.
Alleles and Dominant Genes
Alleles are alternative versions of the same gene with differences in their sequence of DNA bases. These differences account for variations in inherited characteristics.
Sexually reproducing organisms inherit one allele from each parent, and so have a total of two alleles for each gene. When sperm and egg cells are generated, each is given only one allele for each gene. These cells are commonly referred to as haploid cells. When the sperm fertilizes the egg, a cell called a zygote is produced. Zygotes, like most of the cells that subsequently divide, grow and form a complete organism, are referred to as diploid. Generally, when a normal haploid cell contains n chromosomes, the resulting fertilized dipliod cell will contain 2n chromosomes. For more information on specific situations where this does not happen, see nondisjunction.
An organism with two identical copies is said to be homozygous for that gene, and is called a homozygote. An organism with two different alleles for a gene is said to be heterozygous for that gene, and is called a heterozygote.
In a heterozygote, when one allele determines the appearance of the individual it is called the dominant allele. When the other has no noticeable effect it is called the recessive allele. Another term sometimes used for homozygous organisms is "true breeding" because of the certainty that their offspring will possess the given trait. The appearance of a given trait is referred to as the phenotype of the individual, whereas the complete set of alleles (dominant and recessive) is referred to as the genotype.
In reality, a more complex combination of gene expression is common. In some cases, the offspring's appearance is found to be in between the two appearances. This can be seen in cases such as hybrids of red and white roses that can appear pink. This phenomonon is called incomplete dominance.
In other cases, both traits are always visible. This phenomonon is called codominance. Codominance can be seen in blood typing in humans. People may have one or both of two carbohydrates (named A and B, and specified by their particular alleles) attached to the surface of their red blood cells. If neither carbohydrate is present, the person is said to have type O blood. The person is said to have type A blood if the A carbohydrate is present, and type B blood if the B is present. An individual that has inherited A and a B genes, will have both carbohydrates present on all their red blood cells, and is said to have type AB blood.
Transcription and Translation
Most genes contain the information needed to make functional molecules called proteins. A few genes produce other molecules that help the cell assemble proteins. The journey from gene to protein is complex and tightly controlled within each cell. It consists of two major steps: transcription and translation. Together, transcription and translation are known as gene expression.
During the process of transcription, the information stored in a gene’s DNA is transferred to a similar molecule called RNA (ribonucleic acid) in the cell nucleus. The type of RNA that contains the information for making a protein is called messenger RNA (mRNA) because it carries the information, or message, from the DNA out of the nucleus into the cytoplasm.
Translation, the second step in getting from a gene to a protein, takes place in the cytoplasm. The mRNA interacts with a specialized complex called a ribosome, which “reads” the sequence of mRNA bases. Each sequence of three bases, called a codon, usually codes for one particular amino acid. (Amino acids are the building blocks of proteins.) Transfer RNA (tRNA) then assembles the protein, one amino acid at a time. Protein assembly continues until the ribosome encounters a “stop” codon (a sequence of three bases that does not code for an amino acid).
The flow of information from DNA to RNA to proteins is one of the fundamental principles of molecular biology. It is so important that it is sometimes called the “central dogma.”
Molecular Genetics
Gene Structure
Each DNA is made up of the sugar 2'-deoxyribose linked to a phosphate group and one of the four bases: guanine (G), adenine (A), thymine (T), and cytosine (C) These nucleotides are placed in a unique order to code for all of the genes in all living organisms.
Introns
Exons
Mutations
A gene mutation is a permanent change in the DNA sequence that makes up a gene. Mutations range in size from a single DNA building block (DNA base) to a large segment of a chromosome.
Mechanisms of Mutation
Gene mutations occur in two ways: they can be inherited from a parent or acquired during a person’s lifetime. Mutations that are passed from parent to child are called hereditary mutations or germline mutations (because they are present in the egg and sperm cells, which are also called germ cells). This type of mutation is present throughout a person’s life in virtually every cell in the body.
Health and Development
To function correctly, each cell depends on thousands of proteins to do their jobs in the right places at the right times. Sometimes, gene mutations prevent one or more of these proteins from working properly. By changing a gene’s instructions for making a protein, a mutation can cause the protein to malfunction or to be missing entirely. When a mutation alters a protein that plays a critical role in the body, it can disrupt normal development or cause a medical condition. A condition caused by mutations in one or more genes is called a genetic disorder.
In some cases, gene mutations are so severe that they prevent an embryo from surviving until birth. These changes occur in genes that are essential for development, and often disrupt the development of an embryo in its earliest stages. Because these mutations have very serious effects, they are incompatible with life.
It is important to note that genes themselves do not cause disease—genetic disorders are caused by mutations that make a gene function improperly. For example, when people say that someone has “the cystic fibrosis gene,” they are usually referring to a mutated version of the CFTR gene, which causes the disease. All people, including those without cystic fibrosis, have a version of the CFTR gene.
Human Genetics
In humans, genes vary in size from a few hundred DNA bases to more than 2 million bases. The Human Genome Project has estimated that humans have between 20,000 and 25,000 genes. Most genes are the same in all people, but a small number of genes (thought to be less than 1 percent of the total) are slightly different between individuals.
Major sections of this article were taken from the National Library of Medicine's "Genetics Home Reference" Website accessed January 27, 2008.
References:
- ↑ http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/About/primer/genetics_genome.html
- ↑ http://ghr.nlm.nih.gov/handbook/basics/gene
- ↑ [http://www.britannica.com/EBchecked/topic/533811/semantics semantics
- ↑ 4.0 4.1 Neumann-Held EM. (2001) Can it be a “sin” to understand disease? On “genes” and “eugenics” and an “unconnected connection”. Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 4: 5–17.
- Abstract: Particularly, but not exclusively, in Germany, concerns are uttered as to the consequences of modern biotechnological advances and their range of applications in the field of human genetics. Whereas the proponents of this research are mainly focussing on the possible knowledge that could be gained by understanding the causes of developmental processes and of disease on the molecular level, the critics fear the beginnings of a new eugenics movement. Without claiming a logical relationship between genetic sciences and eugenics movements, it is nevertheless suggested in this article that a connection between both can become established when the distinction between scientifically validated statements on one hand and guiding hypotheses and assumptions on the other hand is blurred, as is observed particularly when scientists report their results to the public. This claim is demonstrated in comparisons between the current state of scientific knowledge on the role of genes in development and causation of diseases, and the way this is presented to the public. It is required that a debate on biotechnology should include reflections on the validity of claims made by scientists.
- ↑ 5.0 5.1 Griffiths PE, Stotz K. (2006) GENES IN THE POSTGENOMIC ERA. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 27:499–521.
- ↑ 6.0 6.1 Moss L. (2002) From representational preformationism to the epigenesis of openness to the world? Reflections on a new vision of the organism. Ann. N. Y. Acad. Sci. 981:219-29. PMID PM:12547682.
- Abstract: The problem of how to reconcile the apparent "purposiveness" of the living organism with nonteleological, mechanist modes of explanation was given a certain form through most of the 20th century by a relatively decontextualized understanding of the gene as the heritable determinant of phenotypic traits. As instrumentally preformationist presuppositions about genes give way to the burgeoning elucidation of cell and molecular mechanisms of epigenesis, basic questions about the nature of complex living systems and their evolutionary origins once again come into consideration. Some suggestions are offered for a vision of the genetically recontextualized organism.
- ↑ Wang D. (2005) ‘‘Molecular gene’’: interpretation in the right context. Biology and Philosophy 20:453–464.